The Utilitarian Argument: Ashley Ferguson

When policymakers draft policies and argue for certain initiatives, laws, or programs,

they often contend that their policy will benefit the greatest number of people. This argument is

grounded in utilitarianism, which theorizes that one should pick options that produce the greatest

good for the greatest number [1]. The “good” could be happiness, satisfaction, protection of

human rights, and other benefits brought to humanity. In the context of healthcare, utilitarian

decisions prioritize protecting the health of the greatest number of people. In clinical trials and

research, a utilitarian approach regarding the use of placebos is necessary to protect general

welfare and health. If we want to maximize the care and development of drugs for all, then

placebos must be included in clinical trials and research.

Placebo controls, often used in clinical trials for new drugs, allow for comparison

between two groups: those taking the experimental drug and those not receiving any treatment

[1]. In contemporary clinical medicine, placebo controls have been revered as the “gold

standard” as they enhance accuracy in statistical analysis in clinical trials. Placebos statistically

“yield the strongest efficacy data in drug testing” where bias is minimized and the rigorous

examination of the cause-and-effect relationship between a drug and its outcome is maximized

[2, 3]. The American Medical Association contends that placebo controls can indeed be an

ethical practice, particularly when physicians obtain informed consent [4].

When comparing placebo-controlled trials (PCTs) with other trials that exclude placebos,

specifically active-controlled trials (ACTs), there are severe discrepancies in data that point to

flaws in the methods of ACTs. In antipsychotic drug trials for schizophrenia, the ACTs had a

degree of improvement that was almost double that of drugs in placebo-controlled trials [5]. This

study included 32 trials of typical antipsychotic medications for patients with schizophrenia, and

the degree of improvement, measured by the Brief Psychiatric Rating Scale (BPRS), revealed

that ACTs drastically exaggerated the impacts these medications had on the improvement

patients experienced. ACTs improved about 15 points in the BPRS, and PCTs had mean BPRS

improvements from around 3 to 7 points, with a 6.35 mean difference between the ACT and PCT

scores [5]. In studies comparing two or more active medications without the use of a placebo, the

response rates for active antidepressants were 65.4%—almost 8% higher than similar studies that

have a placebo arm [6]. These results demonstrate that active-control studies have questionable

validity and can overstate and magnify trial results. If these drugs were introduced to the market,

patients would be at risk of consuming drugs that provide no benefit and could, in turn, harm

their health.

The Sean M. Healey & AMG Center for Amyotrophic Lateral Sclerosis (ALS)

Massachusetts General Hospital (MGH) report emphasizes why misinformation and erroneous

data are so damaging. MGM asserts that this data can lead to ineffective or harmful treatments

marketed to the public. It specifically reports that the use of placebos in trials for ALS is

imperative to prevent ineffective or harmful ALS treatments arising in the market [7]. An ACT

for ALS patients indicated that lithium helped slow the disease, but a placebo-controlled, double-

blind trial, proved that lithium had no effect on ALS [7]. This erroneous data arises from trials

that don’t include placebos. If a PCT had not been conducted on lithium for ALS patients, then

this medication would have infiltrated the market.

Interventions that can harm patients are already at risk of being offered and advertised to

the public. A cardiology study examined the impact of a cardiac pacemaker on the risk of

vasovagal syncope, a fainting spell that occurs when the body overreacts to emotional distress

[9]. Unblinded controlled trials of pacemaker therapy compared to an active (standard) treatment

for syncope demonstrated a decrease in the incidence of syncope [9]. The researchers

subsequently interpreted these results as favorable for the use of a pacemaker in reducing

vasovagal syncope. In a follow-up study, however, researchers compared an active pacemaker to

a surgical sham control, a fake surgical intervention—a placebo [9]. This study proved that

active pacing did not reduce the effects of vasovagal syncope [9]. If the original study used a

surgical sham control, fewer patients would have been exposed to the risk of complications of

inserting a pacemaker. If this follow-up study had not been conducted, millions of people

throughout the world could have considered or undergone surgery for a pacemaker that does not

improve their condition and would result in life-threatening risks from unnecessary surgery.

The discussion encompassing placebo use can merge into one false presumption: that the

ethics in PCTs must mirror the ethics of the physician-patient relationship, where the physician

strives for beneficence. Beneficence, the ethical and moral obligation to promote the well-being

of the patient, involves actions to maximize the welfare of the individual a physician is treating.

In the physician-patient relationship, the patient expects the physician to act in his best interest—

to prescribe drugs that will ostensibly benefit the patient. In clinical trials, such as PCTs, the

ultimate goal is to produce a drug that raises and amplifies the well-being of the public—of

society. PCTs, specifically, prioritize producing a drug that will confirm scientific validity so that

the safety of the public—anyone who could receive the drug—is prioritized. Healthcare must

separate the ethics in PCTs and physician-patient relationships because the priority in PCTs to

ensure scientific validity should not be confused by the beneficence expected and required in

physician-patient interactions.

PCTs provide the best insight into whether an active treatment is effective or harmful.

They ensure that the drugs and treatments entering the market are safe, and this fosters trust in

the healthcare system, thus encouraging more people to seek medical care and drugs available on

the market. To further garner this trust, clinical trials should prioritize public safety instead of

sacrificing the validity of research data in the name of ethical research.

The Deontological Argument: Nicholas Cormas

Clinical trials boast prospects of personalized care, financial compensation, and

innovative treatment opportunities for patients with treatable conditions such as Chronic

Obstructive Pulmonary Disease. Unfortunately, rather than receive the novel medications or even

the clinically-accepted treatments, half of clinical trial subjects receive the control treatment––a

placebo pill. A 2017 analysis of all FDA-logged experimental drug and biological product trials

found that 76.9% of Chronic Obstructive Pulmonary Disease trials and the majority of other

medical trials investigating conditions already have pre-existing treatments [1]. Placebo controls

can potentially expose subjects to detrimental side effects of non-treatment, such as ill symptoms

and the worsening of pathology [2]. Accordingly, the implementation of a placebo control often

violates clinical equipoise: an ethical requirement in clinical studies that declares placebo

controls may only be utilized if there is no standard treatment [3]. For example, the principal

investigators of an Indian HIV study of Risperidone as a potential treatment of acute mania were

widely criticized for their choice of a placebo control that exposed subjects to the risks of

untreated HIV during the duration of the study. The principal investigators responded by

claiming that the placebo control was necessary to yield statistically significant results from the

study. This sparked the central point of contention: is it ethical to risk research subjects’ health

via the administration of placebo controls for improved statistical viability of the study [4]?

Given their observed violations of clinical equipoise and patient autonomy, strict placebo

controls in clinical trials are largely unethical and require meticulous scrutiny under the context

of a pre-existing accepted therapy.

To explore the ethical basis of placebo control, I will begin by examining the code of

conduct all physicians swear by: the Hippocratic Oath. The original Hippocratic Oath states that

physicians must “prescribe regimen for the good of [their] patients”, which is often interpreted as

a physician’s pledge to always act in the best interest of their patients [5]. The Hippocratic Oath

is inherently deontological: “a range of rights and obligations [established] because every person

has inherent dignity” [6]. Deontological philosophy is foundational to medical ethics,

encouraging a prioritization of beneficence towards the individual over broader societal concerns

by requiring physicians to ascribe to a specific code of infallible moral values. Accordingly,

withholding treatment via placebo control violates the duty of a physician on two fronts: their

responsibility to act to uphold both the health and autonomy of the individuals they treat [7].

Given the Hippocratic principle of beneficence, it is unethical for a physician to

knowingly withhold a clinically accepted medicine that could function as a control treatment

from a research subject for the betterment of scientific knowledge. This interpretation of the

ancient Hippocratic Oath is corroborated by modern medical institutions. One notable line from

the contemporary Pennsylvania State College of Medicine and the Oceania University of

Medicine Hippocratic Oath reads “I shall not let any lesser public or professional consideration

interfere with my primary commitment” of providing wellness to individual patients [8,9]. In

other words, the sacrifice of complete care for an individual is not ethically justifiable by a claim

that it improves public health for the “greater good.” A physician’s conscious decision to

withhold a clinical accepted therapeutic control treatment by administering a placebo control

goes against the very principle of nonmaleficence that binds physicians to do no harm.

Placebo controls fall short in their ability to maintain patient autonomy. The ideal ethical

standard of any clinical trial is informed consent: research subjects must be fully informed of all

positive and negative consequences of receiving a treatment. Therefore, subjects in a PCT must

be fully informed of the consequences of potentially receiving a placebo treatment. However,

this is often not the case, as seen in a study that analyzed informed consent materials provided to

subjects in 45 large randomized clinical trials [10]. The study found that there was statistically

significant evidence that informed consent materials highly prioritize giving information about

the experimental target treatments over the placebo treatment, deliberately leading patients to

overestimate the potential positive benefits of the experimental treatment whilst underestimating

the possible drawbacks of receiving the placebo control. Only 9% of studies actually described

placebo treatments’ beneficial or adverse effects, and no studies provided subjects with any

rationale as to why or how placebo treatments could affect the subjects’ health [10].

Furthermore, a recent Finnish study found that “an explanation as to why placebo [that] was

necessary [was] featured in only 23% of the sets of participant-information materials, and only

12% of the documents discussed the possible risks associated with placebo” [11]. The global

lack of detailed communication between physicians and research subjects about the rationale and

consequences of placebo control treatment is highly unethical. This failure of clear

communication deals a severe inhibitor of patient autonomy, especially when subjects are

unaware of their clinical right to full autonomy.

These concerns regarding the administration of placebo controls in clinical trials not only

call into question the theoretical ethical basis of PCTs as they have tangible effects on individual

health and public opinion toward medical research. There are still significant gaps in medical

knowledge and consensus about the long-term risks and impact of placebo treatments [12].

Furthermore, patients who receive a placebo control rather than an experimental medicine

designed to treat their condition can quickly lose confidence and trust in the medical system if

complications such as short-term symptoms and long-term developments in their conditions

arise. These emotional complications can be detrimental as the physical effects of placebo

treatment must be seriously addressed. Before we can comfortably administer placebo controls in

good faith, larger strides in communication with patients must be implemented to maximize

autonomy: informing patients of not only what the physiological impacts of placebos but also

why they may receive a placebo control. This must go hand-in-hand with further intensive

research on the long term effects of placebo controls in specific pathologies so that patients are

fully informed of all of the potential consequences of a placebo treatment they may receive.

Among these complexities, one thing remains certain: the very foundation of ethical medicine

crumbles when the wellness and autonomy of patients are compromised for overarching societal

interests in Placebo Controlled Trials.

Ashley’s References:

1. McCombs School of Business. (2024). Utilitarianism. Ethics Unwrapped.

https://ethicsunwrapped.utexas.edu/glossary/utilitarianism

2. Sharona, H. (2001). Connecticut Law Review. Heinonline.org.

https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?collection=journals&handle=hein.journals/conlr33&id=

462&men_tab=srchresults

3. Brower, V. (2001). Science versus ethics. European Molecular Biology Organization.

https://europepmc.org/backend/ptpmcrender.fcgi?accid=PMC1083897&blobtype=pdf

4. Hariton, E., & Locascio, J. J. (2018). Randomised controlled trials - the gold standard for

effectiveness research. BJOG: An International Journal of Obstetrics & Gynaecology,

125(13), 1716. https://doi.org/10.1111/1471-0528.15199

5. American Medical Assocation. (n.d.). Ethical Use of Placebo Controls in Research | ama-

coe. Code of Medical Ethics. https://code-medical-ethics.ama-assn.org/ethics-

opinions/ethical-use-placebo-controls-research

6. Woods, S. W., Gueorguieva, R. V., Baker, C. B., & Makuch, R. W. (2005). Control

Group Bias in Randomized Atypical Antipsychotic Medication Trials for Schizophrenia.

Archives of General Psychiatry, 62(9), 961. https://doi.org/10.1001/archpsyc.62.9.961

7. Hasnain, M., Rudnick, A., Bonnell, W. S., Remington, G., & Lam, R. W. (2018). Use of

Placebo in Clinical Trials of Psychotropic Medication. The Canadian Journal of

Psychiatry, 63(5), 338–341. https://doi.org/10.1177/0706743717752917

8. Sean M. Healey & AMG Center for ALS. (n.d.). Placebo-Controlled Trials.

Massachusetts General Hospital.

https://www.massgeneral.org/neurology/als/research/placebo-

trials#:~:text=So%2C%20why%20use%20placebos%20in

9. Castro, M. (2007). Placebo versus Best-Available-Therapy Control Group in Clinical

Trials for Pharmacologic Therapies: Which Is Better? Proceedings of the American

Thoracic Society, 4(7), 570–573. https://doi.org/10.1513/pats.200706-073jk

Nicholas’s References:

1. Sorscher, S., AbuDagga, A., Almashat, S., Carome, M. A., & Wolfe, S. M. (2018, April

24). Placebo-only-controlled versus active-controlled trials of new drugs F: OAJCT.

Open Access Journal of Clinical Trials. https://www.dovepress.com/placebo-only-

controlled-versus-active-controlled-trials-of-new-drugs-peer-reviewed-fulltext-article-

OAJCT

2. Millum, J., & Grady, C. (2013). The ethics of placebo-controlled trials: methodological

justifications. Contemporary clinical trials, 36(2), 510–514.

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cct.2013.09.003

3. Cassidy, J. T., Petty, R. E., Laxer, R. M., & Lindsley, C. B. (2010). Textbook of Pediatric

Rheumatology E-Book. Elsevier Health Sciences.

4. Basil B, Adetunji B, Mathews M, Budur K. Trial of risperidone in India--concerns. Br J

Psychiatry. 2006 May;188:489-90; author reply 490-1; discussion 491-2. doi:

10.1192/bjp.188.5.489-b. PMID: 16648540.

5. Association of American Physicians and Surgeons. (n.d.). Various physicians oaths.

https://www.aapsonline.org/ethics/oaths.htm#lasagna

6. Centre, T. E. Ethics Explainer: What Is Deontology? https://ethics.org.au/ethics-

explainer-deontology/ (accessed 2024-04-23).

7. Alexander, L., & Moore, M. (2020, October 30). Deontological ethics. Stanford

Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-deontological/

8. Oath of Modern Hippocrates. Penn State College of Medicine Current Students. (2021,

May 11). https://students.med.psu.edu/md-students/oath/

9. Current-2023-Oum Student Handbook. (n.d.).

https://oum.edu.ws/documents/2023/03/oum-student-handbook.pdf/

10. Bishop, F. L., Adams, A. E., Kaptchuk, T. J., & Lewith, G. T. (2012). Informed consent

and placebo effects: a content analysis of information leaflets to identify what clinical

trial participants are told about placebos. PloS one, 7(6), e39661.

https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0039661

11. Keränen, T., Halkoaho, A., Itkonen, E., & Pietilä, A. M. (2015). Placebo-controlled

clinical trials: how trial documents justify the use of randomisation and placebo. BMC

medical ethics, 16, 2. https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-16-2

12. Wyatt, R. J., Henter, I. D., & Bartko, J. J. (1999). The long-term effects of placebo in

patients with chronic schizophrenia. Biological psychiatry, 46(8), 1092–1105.

https://doi.org/10.1016/s0006-3223(99)00227-9

Comment